In Stromateis 2.13-15, Clement of Alexandria addresses the
problem of distinguishing voluntary and involuntary sins. He follows,
through the handbooks available to him, a handful of passages from
Aristotle in which the latter discusses various aspects of this
distinction through the terms ἀτυχεῖν, ἁμαρτάνειν and ἀδικεῖν (NE 1113b-14a; NE 1135b 16-18; EE 1223a 23; and Rhet.
1.13.16). Clement interprets these Aristotelian passages through a
Stoic concept of the passions, as is evident from his quoting a source
very similar to Arius Didymus’ Stoic handbook (Str. 2.13.59.6 = Ar. Did. 2.7.10.1-3; Str.
2.15.63.2 = Ar. Did. 2.7.10a.32). The Stoic point in that handbook was
that passions are impulses that are disobedient to logos, reside in the
hegemonikon, and consequently overpower and tyrannize human conduct.
Clement appropriates Aristotle’s discussion of ἀτυχεῖν, ἁμαρτάνειν and
ἀδικεῖν to explain how this passionate disobedience to logos, which
subsequently tyrannizes us, is in itself up to us.
This appropriation of Aristotle is evidence of an early Christian position, at least in the Alexandrian church, concerning the problems of akrasia and moral progress. Clement’s un-Aristotelian and un-Stoic conclusion deems the phenomenon of akrasia subject to a human authority over deciding between rational and akratic action. This authority over akrasia bears significant implications for Alexandrian Christian anthropology and the subsequent monastic project of attaining theosis through apatheia.
This appropriation of Aristotle is evidence of an early Christian position, at least in the Alexandrian church, concerning the problems of akrasia and moral progress. Clement’s un-Aristotelian and un-Stoic conclusion deems the phenomenon of akrasia subject to a human authority over deciding between rational and akratic action. This authority over akrasia bears significant implications for Alexandrian Christian anthropology and the subsequent monastic project of attaining theosis through apatheia.
No comments:
Post a Comment