Marín, Raúl Villegas, Pseudo-Próspero
de Aquitania Sobre la providencia de Dios. Introducción, texto latinorevisado, traducción y comentario (Publicacions i
Edicions de la
Universitat de Barcelona, 2011). Pp. 346. Paper. €35.00. ISBN 9788447534869.
These days, one expects very little change
in the fifth century. Yet, the figure of Prosper of Aquitaine has changed a
great deal in our day, even a millenium and a half after his death. It is, of
course, not Prosper himself who changes, but our understanding of Prosper that varies,
and Raúl Villegas Marín has contributed to our changing understanding of
Prosper. One of the key claims he defends in his recent study of the fifth
century Carmen de providentia Dei (CDP) is that Prosper did not write this
poem. Given that recent scholarship on Prosper (e.g. A. Hwang, Intrepid Lover, M. Marcovich, De prov. Dei.) accepts Prosperian
authorship of CDP, Marín’s argument
is a significant change within the scholarship. Even apart from questions of
authorship, Marín’s dating of CDP to
the late 420s is also a signficant departure from other scholars, since many
date the work earlier. Dating and authorship are inter-dependent for Marín.
The question of
Prosper’s authorship of CDP is
particularly vexing because the poem favors theological opinions about grace
and free will that other works of Prosper reject. Scholars debate whether
Prosper changed his mind early in his career or whether he was always consistent
with his later defense of St. Augustine’s mature position. Since Augustine is
Prosper’s great hero, it is easy to find a parallel between a Prosper who
changes his mind about the interaction between grace and human will and
Augustine, who also rejected his own earlier views on the subject. Perhaps most
scholars even identify with this kind of development in their own thoughts. It
is not uncommon to change one’s mind. However, Prosper’s conversion would have
happened well after Augustine’s, and so, we struggle to envision a young
Prosper who read the mature Augustine and still fell prey to the same
theological positions which his hero (Augustine) had already rejected. Since CDP would be the earliest and only text
Prosper wrote in defense of the notion that human will sometimes precedes grace,
one’s picture of Prosper is at stake with Marín’s arguments about CDP. If Prosper wrote it, he wrote it
early in the 5th century and then reversed his theologial opinion by
427. If Prosper did not write it, then Prosper’s early career is not marked by
an unannounced shift in opinion, but we must find another plausible explanation
for its authorship.
Marín argues
that CDP was not written by an
inconsistent Prosper, but rather was written by one of Prosper’s opponents
sometime around 426/427. This
position is internally consistent. Dating CDP
to c. 416, which is the current
majority opinion, is internally consistent with Prosperian authorship, provided
that Prosper changes his mind. Marín is careful to note that Augustine’s change
of position is not a good parallel, as other scholars have attempted to argue,
because Prosper does not offer a retractio
(p56). Instead of presenting himself as having a change of position, Prosper
speaks of theological enemies who hold heretical positions. The basic form of
Prosper’s “later” claims makes it difficult to hold that the CDP is, in fact, an “earlier” text of
Prosper’s. Prosperian texts like his letter to Augustine and de ingrat. speak of the positions
presented in CDP as positions other people hold. Furthermore,
Prosperian texts from the late 420s argue that the positions presented in CDP are heretical. This indicates not
that Prosper’s position on grace and free will developed, but that he
consistently rejected the theology of his Gallic neighbors. Additionally, those
who argue for Prosperian authorship on philological grounds find a tough critic
in Marín. His response to this scholarship is well formed (p55-59); We expect strikingly
similar vocabulary from a range of authors who are arguing about the same
technical terms. Use of these technical terms is not enough to establish Prosperian
authorship because several authors use them. In short, Marín’s thesis that
Prosper cannot be the author of this text depends on his arguments that the
theology of the CDP is not Prosper’s
theology. He is not alone in this position (p62), but much rests on dating the
text later rather than earlier so that there is no chance for Prosper to change
his mind.
The theology of CDP certainly fits the theologial milieu which Marín articulates. But CDP laments the destruction which has
come about from political instability and war. Scholars have been very happy to
see the civil unrest described in the poem as the result of the complicated
“barbarian” military and political activity of the early fifth century
(pp1-23). The reference to suffering under Vandal swords for ten years fits
with the date 416 for the poem. This directly contradicts Marín’s thesis. Marín
is at his weakest when having to intepret caede
decennis / Vandalicis gladiis sternimur et Geticis as meaning something
less literal (p 53, 144-145). However, his arguments for dating the text based
on its use of and response to other theological texts is more convincing. Marín
argues that the text is later than the Papal condemnations of Pelagianism in
417 and 418 (p39-40) because CDP
accepts the Roman position. Once we grant that CDP is later than 418, it becomes apparent that CDP belongs to the discussion that
occured at end of the 420s. CDP fits
theologically with Augustine’s de corr., Cassian’s
Coll. 13, and Prosper’s contentious
and vociferous response to his fellow Gallic theologians (p47-55). The text
cannot belong to Prosper. Thus, Marín argues that it is easier to read decinnis figuratively than to suppose
the theology is prescient of a decade of Gallo-Roman discussions influenced by
African sources.
Marín considers
that the text could have circulated anonymously (which makes it easier to
explain various attributions in manuscripts, p55-63), but ultimately suggests
that it was written by a monk at St. Victor’s monastery under Cassian (p63-70).
Still, one finishes Marín’s work wishing the constraints of time and space had
not forced him to omit more speculation on how his argument impacts our picture
of Prosper. The focus of his work on the text and not the man made it possible
for Marín to format his work with 74 pages of introduction which summarize the
220 pages of line-by-line commentary on the poem. One must constantly flip from
the thematically organized introduction to the more detailed discussions of individual
phrases as though the commentary were endnotes for the introduction. Marín’s insightful
discussion is sometimes complicated by the multiplicity of passages from within
his book which must be held in the reader’s mind, but his contribution to
scholarship on the issue will be appreciated by all who read it, as will his
translation, the first in a modern Romance language.
Thomas Humphries, Saint Leo, USA
This is an utterly baffling and baffled review. I am particularly interested to know where in the De Providentia do you or does Marin say that Prosper defends the notion that human will sometimes precedes grace? How did the reviewer not notice that apart from Marin's ludicrous suggestion that the decade of war would be an allusion to the Trojan war, his arguments dismissing Hincmar's identification of Prosper as the poem's author and hypothesis that it was smuggled into the and transmitted in the Prosperian corpus by antiaugustinian monks to be specious and utterly self-serving?
ReplyDelete